Our bookstore now ships internationally. Free domestic shipping $50+ →

The Rudolf Steiner Archive

a project of Steiner Online Library, a public charity

Your search for kant -hegel returned 318 results

3. Truth and Knowledge (1963): Epistemology Since Kant
Tr. Rita Stebbing

Rudolf Steiner
All propounders of theories of knowledge since Kant have been influenced to a greater or lesser degree by the mistaken way he formulated the problem of knowledge.
I believe this definition comes nearest to the meaning of this concept as it has been used in philosophy, with greater or lesser clarity, ever since Kant. Critical reflection then is the opposite of the naive approach. A critical attitude is one that comes to grips with the laws of its own activity in order to discover their reliability and limits.
3. Truth and Science: Epistemology Since Kant
Tr. John Riedel

Rudolf Steiner
All epistemologists after Kant have been influenced to a greater or lesser extent by Kant’s flawed reasoning. Kant’s view (that all objects given to us are merely our mental representations) arises due to his a priori stance.
We believe that this best captures the meaning of the term critical, as it has become established in philosophy with various degrees of clarity since Kant. Critical prudence is therefore the opposite of naïveté. We call behavior critical when it takes control of the laws of one's own activity, to learn about their safety and limits.
Otto Liebmann, Zur Analysis, p. 28 ff. of the German ed48. Vokelt, Kant’s Erkenntnistheorie, section 1.49. J. Rehmke, Die Welt als Wahrnehmung und Begriff uns; Berlin 1880.
3. Truth and Knowledge (1963): Kant's Basic Epistemological Question
Tr. Rita Stebbing

Rudolf Steiner
Kant is generally considered to be the founder of epistemology in the modern sense. However, the history of philosophy before Kant contains a number of investigations which must be considered as more than mere beginnings of such a science.
Kant, Prolegomena, Sec. v.5. Kant, Kritik, p. 53 f. of the German ed.
10. Kant, Kritik, p. 58, Sec. v.11. Hermann Cohen (1842–1918), Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, Kant's Theory of Experience, Berlin, 1871, pp. 90 ff. of the German ed.
353. From Beetroot to Buddhism: Kant, Schopenhauer and Eduard von Hartmann 14 May 1924, Dornach
Tr. Anna R. Meuss

Rudolf Steiner
Mr Burle: We've had the (200th) anniversary of Kant's birthday.71 1 May I ask Dr Steiner to tell us something about Kant's teaching, what would be its opposites, and if it might today be an anthroposophical teaching?
And so I would read Kant whilst the teacher was teaching history. I therefore also felt perfectly confident to speak about Kant, of whom people really always say when something to do with mind and spirit comes up: 'Yes, but Kant said...'
Then he would wake up, jump up like a jack-in-the-box and shout: 'But Kant said!' And so it is true that people go on a great deal about Kant. Now let us consider how this man Kant really saw the world.
3. Truth and Science: Kant's Theory of Knowing's Basic Questions
Tr. John Riedel

Rudolf Steiner
Kant is usually cited as the founder of the theory of knowing (Erkenntnistheorie) 24 in the modern sense of the word.
Then Kant's theory lacks any basis. Everything Kant puts forward in the five paragraphs that precede the formulation of his basic question is an attempt to prove that mathematical judgments are synthetic.
Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, p. 58, Sec. v.38. Hermann Cohen (1842–1918), Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, Kant's Theory of Experience, Berlin, 1871, pp. 90 ff. of the German ed.
52. Epistemological Foundation of Theosophy II 04 Dec 1903, Berlin

Rudolf Steiner
The human being with his average mental capacity cannot realise the spirit; but it is said that one can assume such a common life with a spiritual world. With such a view Kant’s epistemology is not compatible. He who wrote the foundation of this view is Immanuel Kant himself.
The oscillations follow each other outside. Physics does not go so far as Kant. Whether the “things-in-themselves” are space-filled whether they are in space or follow each other in time, we cannot know—in terms of Kant; but we know only: we are organised this and that way, and, therefore, something—may it be spatial or not—has to take on spatial form.
He had developed an own view from Kant’s critique of reason: if we look at the world, we find contradictions there. Let us have a look at the own ego.
6. Goethe's Conception of the World: Consequences of the Platonic View of the World
Tr. Harry Collison

Rudolf Steiner
Mistrust of the world of perception is present in Kant also. These thought-habits of Kant are further influenced by Hume. Kant admits that Hume is right when the latter asserts that the ideas into which thought unites the single perceptions are not derived from experience but that they are added by thought to experience.
Kant, however, renounces the conception that the ideas open up a true insight into the essential being of the universe if only there remains to them the attribute of eternity and necessity.
Kant's philosophical mode of conception was nourished in a yet higher degree by the trend of his religious sense.
6. Goethe's World View: The Consequences of the Platonic World View
Tr. William Lindemann

Rudolf Steiner
Mistrust toward the world of perception is also present in Kant. To these habits of thinking there is added the influence of Hume. Kant agrees with Hume with respect to his assertion that the ideas into which thinking combines the individual perceptions do not stem from experience, but rather that thinking adds them to experience.
Kant, however, renounces the notion that ideas open any real insight into the being of the world, just so they retain the quality of the eternal and necessary.
* Kant's philosophical way of picturing things was in addition particularly nourished by the direction of his religious feelings.
2. The Science of Knowing: Intellect and Reason
Tr. William Lindemann

Rudolf Steiner
But this does not apply to ideas themselves. For Kant these do not have even this degree of objectivity. Kant finds that the principles of mathematics and of pure natural science are such valid synthetical principles a priori.
In 7 and 5 the sum 12 is in no way contained, concludes Kant. I must go beyond 7 and 5 and call upon my intuition; [ Anschauung—“Intuition” is the conventional translation of Kant's Anschauang.
It is exactly the same with the geometrical example Kant presents. A limited straight line with end points A and B is an indivisible unit. My intellect can form two concepts of it.
2. A Theory of Knowledge: Intellect and Reason
Tr. Olin D. Wannamaker

Rudolf Steiner
Kant, therefore, designated ideas, not as constitutive principles which must be determinative for things, but as regulative principles which have meaning and significance only for the systematics of our knowledge.
But this principle cannot be applied to ideas themselves. According to Kant these never possess that degree of objectivity. Kant decides that the propositions of mathematics and pure natural science are a priori such valid propositions.
The same is true of the geometrical examples cited by Kant. A limited straight line with the termini A and B is an indivisible unit. My intellect can form two concepts of this.

Results 1 through 10 of 318

1 2 3 4 5 6 ... 32 ˃